The use of Kant’s critique of syllogism in argumentation
Abstract
Categorical syllogism is arguably the longest-studied form of deductive reasoning. Classical syllogistic theory was mostly focused on discovering structural nuances of syllogism and paid significantly less attention to the prospect of practical and everyday use of such reasoning in arguments. This is especially evident in the way classical syllogistics sorts syllogisms into four distinct figures, as the rules assigned to each figure tell only how to recognize each figure when it is presented and nearly nothing about when and why to use a particular figure in practice. Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) published a succinct critique of this approach, accusing it of creating false subtleties that obscure more than they clear things up. In turn, he offered his own theory that radically reduces the complexity of syllogistic rules to only two principles: the affirmative rule which states that the characteristic mark of a characteristic mark is a characteristic mark of the thing itself; and the negative rule which states that that which contradicts the characteristic mark of a thing contradicts the thing itself. Following Kant’s reduction, one can reconstruct a heuristic to help with the use of syllogisms in arguments. The two principles display important parallels with the relations of sufficient and necessary conditions, as both principles and both conditions have the same transitive property that enables them to be expressed as material implication. This shows that modes of first syllogistic figure can be used in arguments that deal with sufficient conditions being satisfied, modes of second syllogistic figure can be used in arguments that deal with necessary conditions being breached, modes of third figure can be used in arguments dealing with the absolute minimum for satisfying sufficient conditions, and ultimately, modes of fourth figure can be used in cases when one needs to argue for an alternative perspective to one of the previous figures.
References
Aristotel (2008). Analitika I-II; Kategorije; O izrazu. Paideia.
Cauman, L. S. (2004). Uvod u logiku prvog reda. Naklada Jesenski i Turk.
Dickstein, L. (1978). The effect of figure on syllogistic reasoning. Memory & Cognition, 6(1), 76–83.
Harli, P. (2012). Kratak uvod u logiku. Zavod za udžbenike.
Kant, I. (1912). Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistische Figuren. In Kant’s gesammelte Schriften (Vol. II, pp. 45–61). Georg Reimer.
Kant, I. (2003). Kritika čistoga uma. Dereta.
Khemlani, S., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2012). Theories of the syllogism: A meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin, 138(3), 427–457.
Koen, M., & Nejgel, E. (2006). Uvod u logiku i naučni metod. Jasen.
Lambert, J. H. (1764). Neues Organon, Erster Band. Johann Wendler.
Lemon, E. Dž. (2002). Upoznavanje sa logikom. Jasen.
Mill, J. S. (1851). A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive (Vol. I). John Parker.
Petrović, G. (2003). Logika. Dnevnik – Novine i časopisi / Zavod za udžbenike i nastavna sredstva.
Rujević, G. (2016). Savršenstvo prve figure. Zbornik Matice srpske za klasične studije, 18, 151–163.
Schönfeld, M. (2000). The philosophy of the young Kant. Oxford University Press.
Šešić, B. (1983). Osnovi logike. Naučna knjiga.
Vanzo, A. (2018). Kant’s False subtlety of the four syllogistic figures in its intellectual context. In M. Sgarbi & M. Cosci (Eds.), The aftermath of syllogism. Bloomsbury Academic.
Zaječaranović, G. (1996). Logika. Izdavačka jedinica Univerziteta u Nišu.
Wolff, Ch. (1732). Philosophia Rationalis Sive Logica. Renger.
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License.